Identity of Indiscernibles


As we saw in class, and in principle (7) on this handout here, Leibniz's Law is a bi-conditional that claims the following: Necessarily, for anything, x, and anything, y, x is identical to y if and only if for any property x has, y has, and for any property y has, x has.

Because this is a bi-conditional, it is comprised of two different conditionals, (i) and (ii):

(i) If x is identical to y, then for any property x has, y has and for any property y has, x has.
(ii) If for any property x has, y has, and for any property y has, x has, then x is identical to y.


The Indiscernibility of Identicals

(i) is called the Indiscernibility of Identicals because it claims that self-identical object(s) must be indiscernible from themselves. It is a fairly uncontroversial thesis. I say "fairly" because there are philosophers who deny this claim. We will discuss some of these philosophers and their views as the semester progresses.

Almost everyone else, however, will grant that if something, x, is identical with something, y, then x and y have all of the same properties; x and y are just one thing, after all, merely called by two different names "x" and "y." If Superman is identical to Clark Kent, for example, then Superman wears glasses and Clark Kent has x-ray vision because Clark Kent wears glasses and Superman has x-ray vision. Since Superman is identical to Clark Kent, there is no property that Superman has that Clark Kent doesn't have, since "they" are just one guy, not two.

Notice that another way to put the Indiscernibility of Identicals is in terms of qualitative and numerical identity (which was discussed in class and in this handout here). The Indiscernibility of Identicals says: If x and y are numerically identical, then x and y are qualitatively identical.


The Identity of Indiscernibles

(ii) is called the Identity of Indiscernibles because it claims that indiscernible objects must be identical. This thesis has raised quite a bit of debate among metaphysicians. You might think it is intuitive because of its practical applications: it seems that we do in fact use this principle when we are trying to determine whether we've got one thing in front of us or two. For example, suppose we are trying to figure out whether Superman is identical to Clark Kent. We begin: "Well, Superman is 6ft tall, and Clark Kent is 6 ft tall; Superman has dark hair and dark eyes, and Clark Kent has dark hair and dark eyes; Superman can't get injured by fire and--look!--Clark Kent can't get injured by fire, either!", etc. If a certain identity such as Clark Kent = Superman is not known, then tallying all of the properties that "each" has and seeing if there is a property that one has that "the other" doesn't, will aid us in determining whether Clark Kent is in fact Superman.

We might also think that that the Identity of Indiscernibles is right because we think, intuitively, that if there are in fact two, distinct things, there must be something--some property or quality--that makes them different. It is explanatorily helpful, in other words, to claim that distinct objects are distinct because they have at least one property that makes them distinct. To put it another way: if the Identity of Indiscernibles was false, then that would mean that we could have a world with two or ten or a hundred qualitatively identical things, but there would be no feature to distinguish between such worlds except by stipulation--i.e., we would just have to stipulate that there are two as opposed to ten or a hundred qualitatively identical things, since there is no quality in the things themselves that would explain the difference between two or ten or a hundred qualitatively identical things.

Similar to the Indiscernibility of Identicals, notice that another way to put the Identity of Indiscernibles is in terms of qualitative and numerical identity: If x and y are qualitatively identical, then x and y are numerically identical.



Trouble for the Identity of Indiscernibles

However, as intuitive as the Identity of Indiscernibles may be, there seem to be a host of counterexamples. Most famously is Max Black's Balls, which you can read in his article, "The Identity of Indiscernibles" [note: this is a link through jstor, so you may need to be on campus or using a university proxy server to follow it].

Roughly, the idea is this: Imagine a possible world that contains just two perfectly round symmetrical spheres. The spheres have the same diameter, they are an equal distance from each other, they are the only inhabitants of a completely symmetrical universe, they are both made of solid iron, etc. Intuitively, such spheres in such a world would have all and only the same properties; they are qualitatively identical. Yet, by stipulation, there is supposedly two of these spheres, not one. But if "they" are qualitatively identical, then by the Identity of Indiscernibles, "they" are numerically identical; "they" are one, and not two. Thus, either there cannot be a world where there are two qualitatively identical objects or else the Identity of Indiscernibles is false. Since it seems that we can imagine a world with two numerically distinct yet qualitatively identical objects, then the Identity of Indiscernibles must be false.


Response #1

Recall in class that some people suggested that we might be able to distinguish between the two spheres because one of them might have the property "the property of being identical to sphere a" or "the property of being distinct from sphere b" or "the property of being this sphere and not another," etc. Such a move would be appealing to individual essences or "thisnesses" or "haecceities", and would block the counterexample, but at the cost of inviting still more problems.

Problem 1: Suppose you are a materialist--you believe that there is only physical stuff in the universe. Or, even weaker, suppose that you are a materialist only when it comes to material objects such as rocks and trees and spheres and the like (you are agnostic or a dualist when it comes to people, say). What are you to make of haecceities? If we take away material bits of a  (merely)  material object like a sphere--if we remove one metallic bit of it one by one, and one at a time--where is the haecceity? A commitment to haecceities is skirting dangerously close to a sort of dualism for objects, which might rub more conservative ontologists the wrong way.

 Problem 2: If you endorse individual essences or haecceities then you seemingly save the Identity of Indiscernibles, but you have to ultimately bite the bullet and admit that it is impossible for there to be a world with two qualitatively identical spheres. So you will have to explain why it is that it certainly seems as if we can imagine such a world.

Problem 3: Imagine a world with just one sphere. According to the haecceitist, there is just one haecceity or thisness or individual essence. Now imagine that the sphere morphs like an amoebae and splits itself in half. Each half now morphs into a small sphere, each seemingly qualitatively like the other. No new material is made; no old material disappears. The original sphere is simply changing shape and reforming itself out of the material that was already in the universe. Now we have a world that seemingly has two qualitatively identical spheres. According to the haecceitist, there must now be two haecceities. But where did the second haecceity come from? By stipulation, the world began with just one! A haecceitist may bite the bullet and say that there was always two, but this seems unmotivated: if the sphere had never morphed there would not be a need to posit two haecceities!

Besides, imagine that after the sphere morphs into two spheres, each sphere morphs again into two, making four (seemingly) indiscernible spheres. So now, according to the haecceitist, there are four haecceities to account for the four spheres. But where did these other haecceities come from? If the haecceitist insists that there were always four, then this seems as unmotivated as saying that there were always two haecceities. And it seems that we can keep morphing the spheres, ad infinitum, forcing the haecceitist to ultimately say that there are infinitely many haecceities in just one sphere! If we thought a commitment to just one haecceity for one sphere was ontologically suspicious, positing infinitely many is surely even worse!

Problem 4: Positing haecceities seems ad hoc. Do we have any other reason to posit these weird, suspicious "thisnesses" except to save the Identity of  Indiscernibles? If the haecceitist can provide no other reason for positing individual essences other than to save the Identity of Indiscernibles, we may wonder why the principle was worth saving in the first place.

 Problem 5: Positing haecceities seems to make the Identity of Indiscernibles trivially true. This is a problem if you thought that the principle was supposed to be substantial, metaphysical thesis.


Response #2

Another response that was suggested in class was that we might be able to distinguish the spheres by location. However, the world was stipulated to be a symmetrical one, and the twin spheres were lonely twins--they were the only inhabitants in the entire world. So this means that we cannot specify their location relative to anything else in the universe. So, someone might suggest, the spheres are located at distinct absolute locations of space-time points.

Problem 1: our best scientific theories suggest that that the universe cannot have anything like absolute location.

Problem 2: even if such a suggestion didn't contradict the best scientific theories of the day, it would be odd to think that mere a priori reflection on the identity relation would yield as substantial a metaphysical (and physical!) thesis about whether space was absolute or not.

Problem 3: this response requires that we accept distinctness of space-time points as primitive. Yet if we are going to do this, why not accept distinctness of individuals as primitives as the haecceitist does? What's the real difference, in other words, between individual essences of objects and individual essences of space-time points? If we had problems with haecceities, it seems these problems would repeat themselves at the level of primitively distinct space-time points.


Response #3

A third response (that we only briefly mentioned in class) is to claim that the counterexample was set up incorrectly. The mistake, you might claim, was in claiming that there are two spheres in the possible world under consideration. Claiming that there are two spheres already begs the questions against someone who accepts the Identity of Indiscernibles. Rather, there are not "two" qualitatively identical spheres, but just one sphere that happens to be bi-located--i.e., one sphere in two places at the same time.

Problem 1: This violates a counterpart to our principle (6) in this handout here. Principle (6) said that no two material objects can occupy the same place at the same time. A counterpart of this principle says: no material object can be at two places at the same time. Let us call this principle P. Accepting that objects can be bi-located would violated this principle. So we might ask ourselves: which do we think is more intuitive? The Identity of Indiscernibles? Or principle P? Common sense seems to favor principle P; so the Identity of Indiscernibles should be abandoned.

Problem 2: Suppose objects can be bi-located, and that Max Black's supposed counterexample is merely a description of a world where one sphere is bi-located. Now imagine that someone came along and spit in the direction of one of the locations of the bi-located sphere. What happens to the sphere at the opposite location? Does it get spit on, too? How would that be? The person just spit once, in one direction. Yet if there really is just one sphere there (even if it is bi-located) then, by the Indiscernibility of Identicals, it can't have any properties dissimilar from itself. Yet now it does: it (in one location) was just spit upon yet it (in the other location) wasn't. Surely this just goes to show that there are two spheres in this world, not one!



References:

Max Black, "Identity of Indiscernibles," Mind, vol. LXI, no. 242, 1952.
Jason Bowers, personal notes and correspondance 2006-08.


Page Last Updated: Jan. 24, 2008
Back to Phil 330 Main Page
Back to Meg's Teaching Page
Back to Meg's Main Page