Summary of "The Makropulos Case"


Williams wants to argue that immortality--or a life without death--would be meaningless, or that death gives meaning to life. Let us call this position the Makropolus Position:

Makropolus Position: that death gives life meaning, and that an immortal life would be meaningless.

Williams begins by presenting two arguments in favor of an opposing position, one which we have called in class the Epicurean View:

Epicurean View: death is neither an evil nor a good; it neither makes life meaningful nor meaningles; death is nothing to us.

(Notice that the Epicurean view technically says that death is evaluatively neutral--i.e., it is neither an evil nor a good. In this article, however, and in a majority of the others we will be looking at, we are primarily concerned with whether death is an evil. So we have left discussion of whether death is a good alone for now. However, do notice that the following discussion could be run concerning death as good, as opposed to evil. You might see for yourself whether you think parallel moves can be made if someone were to try to argue that death was a good thing, and consider why someone might think this.)

Williams' strategy is to show how the two arguments for the Epicurean View fail, and how this fact, together with some additional considerations, buttress support for the Makropolus Position. The two arguments in support of the Epicurean view are as follows:

Argument 1:   

(1) If death is an evil, then we must experience it as evil.
(2) Death is an experiential blank; we can never experience death as evil.
(C) Therefore, death is not an evil.

Argument 2:  

(1) If death is an evil, then more of it should make a difference than less of it--i.e., we should prefer less death than more.
(2) Once you are dead, you are dead for the same amount of time--FOREVER--so more of it doesn't make a difference than less of it.
(C) Therefore, death is not an evil.

In Argument 1, premise (1) follows from a general Epicurean Priniple:

Epicurean Principle: something is good or bad for a person if and only if that person experiences it as good or bad; nothing can be bad for a person if that person does not experience it as bad.

We talked about the Epicurean Principle in relation to Nagel's article, "Death." Recall that Nagel argued against this principle because he thought that there were plenty of counterexamples: lies, betrayal, infidelity, etc., are all cases where it seems that something is bad for a person, even if that person never finds out. So given what Nagel says in his article, we can assume that he would reject premise (1) of Argument 1.

But what about Argument 2? Premise (1) seems pretty intuitive: usually, if something is evil, then more of it will make a difference--i.e., we would prefer less of it than more.  One murder is bad; more murders
is even worse. Getting an F in class is bad; getting more Fs is even worse, etc.  And premise (2) seems intuitive as well: if once you are dead, you are dead forever, then being dead one year more or less really won't make a difference in the amount of time you are dead--it is still for eternity either way.

Williams, however, thinks that there are several things wrong with Argument 2. First, he thinks that there is a dangerous tension between Argument 1 and Argument 2--he thinks that Argument 2 indirectly contradcts Argument (1). To show this, Wiliams claims that premise (2) of Argument 2 implies the following counterfactual (*):

(*) If there were a finite period of death (i.e., if death were not eternal), such that if you died later rather then sooner then you would be dead for less time, then there would be a point to wanting to die later rather than earlier.

And Williams thinks that (*) can only be true if there is something wrong with the condition of being dead. But this is exactly what is denied by Argument 1! There is nothing that it is like to be dead; death is an experiential blank!

Response

One might respond to Williams as follows: "By definition, death cannot be a finite period of time. Death is the permanent cessation of life. So it is logically impossible for death to be of finite duration. Thus, (*) has a logically impossible antecedent. Entertaining such a counterpossible would be as absurd as entertaining the counterpossible "If 2 +2 = 5, then ______." So Argument 2 cannot imply (*), unless there is an absurdity in Argument 2 itself, in which case it would be open to a redutio ad absurdum. Since it is not, (*) is neither here nor there, and is of no concern to the Epicurean."

However, Williams has a second, less contentious charge against the arguments for the Epicurean View. He charges that the Epicurean will admit that there are goods in life--praemia vitae. We have goals and desires and needs, and when these are accomplished, there is an uncontroversial positive value to our life. Being conscious of the rewards and delights of life is itself a reward and delight, and even the Epicurean will admit as much. But, if this is right (Williams argues) then being around longer--staving off death for as long as possible--living longer so that you can reap these goods in life is prefeable to having a life cut short. So, a longer life is, all else being equal, better than a shorter one. And so a later death is prefered to a sooner one. But this directly contradticts premise (2) of Argument 2, and so something must be wrong with Argument (2).

To further support the claim that a longer life is prefered to a shorter one, Williams presents the following principle:

Principle of Desire: If I desire something, then (other things being equal) I prefer a state of affairs in which I get it from one in which I do not.

Suppose the Principle of Desire is true. Well, no matter what the desire (so Williams argues), a situation in which I am alive rather than dead is one in which I might get what I desire. In other words, being dead is guarenteed to frustrate any desire I have, and so given the Principle of Desire, I will prefer situations in which I am alive over ones in which I am not. So wanting anything is a reason to avoid death. Knowing that death will frustrate any of your wants and desires is enough to make death an evil, from the point of view of a wanting agent. All wants are conditional on being alive.

However, Williams does not exactly endorse the above argument himself; he seems to think there is something appealing about it, but in the end thinks that one can have categorical, as opposed to a conditional desire. In the case of suicide, for example, it may just be that an individual has the categorical desire not to live, and this better not be conditional upon anything else. He also raises the possibility of an ascetic who has the brute, categorical desire to live. But none of this really matters, Williams thinks, since we may be able to cash out the difference in terms of possible worlds.

[to be continued...]

Page Last Updated: 4/15/08
Back to Phil 330 S 08
Back to Meg's Teaching Page
Back to Meg's Main Page