Coincident Entities
Quick Notes on Wiggins, Doepke, and Johnston
in Rea's Material Constitution: A Reader

Wiggins:

Wiggins begins by drawing our attention to our Commonsense Truism (6), or what he calls S.

S: two things cannot completely occupy exactly the same place or exactly the same volume (or exactly the same subvolumes within exactly the same volume) for exactly the same period of time.

He discusses two examples that would not count as counterexamples to S:

    (i) A man and his forearm.
    (ii) A sponge saturated with water.

(i) does not count as a counterexample to S because a man and his forearm do not completely occupy exactly the same place at the same time. (ii) does not count as a counterexample because the water molecules that saturate a sponge do not occupy the small subvolumes within the volume that the sponge occupies; anywhere a bit of sponge is, water isn't, and anywhere water is, the sponge isn't.

However, Wiggins continues, perhaps the following is a counterexample to S:

The Tree and the Cellulose: Imagine that there is a tree, T, that occupies a certain volume, v1, at a certain time, t1. However, at t1, v1 is also occupied by an aggregate of cellulose molecules, W. Thus, T and W are completely occupying the same place at the same time. Moreover, we know that T is not identical to W because of Leibniz's Law. We could imagine that the tree is thrown into the wood chipper, but none of the cellulose molecules are destroyed. In this way, W has the property of being able to survive if thrown in a wood chipper, while T does not. Moreover, the tree could undergo a pruning, and have some of its branches removed, and yet still survive, whereas the aggregate of cellulose molecules would be destroyed. Thus, T has the property of being able to survive a pruning, while W does not. Thus, since there is at least one property that W and T don't share, by Leibniz's Law, W is not identical to T. But then this will violate principle S.

Wiggins thinks that there is still something right about principle S, even if the tree and cellulose example seem to be a definitive counterexample to it. He thinks that we can amend S to accommodate purported counterexamples if we relativize S to kinds or types (or sortals), yielding what he calls S*:

S*: No two things of the same kind (that is, no two things which satisfy the same sortal or substance concept) can occupy exactly the same volume at exactly the same time.

Wiggins thinks that S* is "a sort of necessary truth"--that is, he thinks that is cannot fail to be true. Notice that S* allows for two things to be in he same place at the same time, provided these two things are two different kinds (or sortals or substance concepts). Hence, Wiggins' view is one that endorses coincident entities. He also thinks that adopting S*, or replacing our principle (6) with S*, will provide us with solutions to our four Puzzles of Objects. In particular, he thinks that S* helps solve the case of Tib and Tibbles.


Questions: How, exactly, is S* supposed to help solve the puzzle of Tib and Tibbles? Is this a satisfying solution? Why or why not? How does this solve the other puzzles--e.g., the Debtor's Paradox, Goliath and Lumpl, and the Ship of Theseus? Do you think that embrace S* is as counterintuitive as giving up S, our our principle (6)? Can you think of any counterexamples to S*? Discussion in class.


Doepke:

Like Wiggins, Doepke also thinks that the source of our trouble when we are considering puzzles of material objects such as Tib and Tibbles, Goliath and Lumpl, etc., is our commonsense principle (6). His project in his article "Spatially Coinciding Objects" is to take some of the bite out of rejecting principle (6) and maintaining that two objects (of two different kinds) can occupy the same place at the same time.

Doepke first canvasses several examples--e.g., a man and his body, a ship and the wooden planks that make up the ship, a statue and the lump of clay that constitutes the statue, etc.--and demonstrates how Leibniz's Law will easily show us that in each case, the the two entities under consideration are distinct. Hence, in each case we are dealing with (at least) two objects, not one.

However, Doepke realizes that there are at least four different ways someone might try to block the conclusion that, in the puzzles under consideration, there really are two distinct objects occupying the same place at the same time. In other words, there are four ways someone might argue that our principle (6) is true, and that  resorting to coincident entities is unnecessary and avoidable. These ways are as follows:

1. The One-Many View: claims that in each of the puzzle cases, there is only one singular object in question, not two.
2. The Relative Identity View (both the Temporal Version and the Sortal Version): modifies Leibniz's Law.
3. The Diachronic View: denies that the two objects exist at the same time.
4. The Reductivist View: revises the commitments of ordinary talk about material objects.

Since we will be discussing each of (1)-(4) in more detail in the following weeks, I will only mention the positions here. Doepke's strategy is one of elimination: he goes through each of these positions one by one and shows how he thinks that each can be refuted. In the process, he thinks it is revealed how it could be the there are coincident entities--i.e., how it could be that two things are in the same place at the same time, by looking at how such collocated, distinct things might be related. His aim is that in looking at his (and Wiggins' view) in contrast to the alternatives will show how the coincident entity view is less unintuitive than may have first been supposed.

A couple of points to highlight, and questions to consider:

(a) In discussing the One-Many view, the distinction is made between singular referring expressions and plural referring expressions. We will talk about this in class and it will be explained briefly on the Useful Terms and Concepts page here.

(b) Doepke discusses two Relative Identity Views: a temporal version and a sortal version. We will be discussing both of these views in more detail, but Doepke gives a nice, quick summary of each if you were looking for a preliminary look at some of the material we will be covering in the next couple of weeks.

(c) In his discussion of the sortal relativity view, Doepke claims that certain pairs of objects--like you and your body, or a ship and the wood that constitutes the ship--might share parts, but that they do not share all of their parts. He claims, for instance, that you might be made up of molecules, and it might seem as if you and your molecules have all of the same parts--after all, where you are, there some molecules are, etc. But he thinks that you have some parts that the molecules constituting you don't have: you have a heart as a part, whereas the molecules constituting you do not have a heart as a part. Similarly, he thinks that a ship may have some boards as parts, but he doesn't think that the wood that constitutes the ship has boards as parts. "Though every part of the collection of [molecules] is a part of you and every part of the wood is a part of the ship, you and the ship have 'additional' parts not shared by the collection of [molecules] and the wood." p. 16 (MC) Think about this line of reasoning. Can you see any problem with it? Suppose, for example, that unlike Wiggins and Doepke (and Johnston) you disagree that constitution is not identity. That is, suppose that you disagree that in the various Puzzles of Objects we have been considering that there are always two distinct objects occupying the same place at the same time. What might be your response to Doepke's little argument above?

Note: Doepke uses the above argument to prove a different point than the one I am highlighting, but I wanted to draw your attention to the fact that constitution puzzles--e.g., ones about you and your body, or a ship and the wood that constitutes the ship, etc.--can often repeat themselves at the 'part' level.
(d) Notice that the Diachronic view is one way of denying our commonsense principle (3): an object can gain and lose parts and still remain the same object. For insofar as our principle (3) allows that an object can change a little bit, the Diachronic view (as describe by Doepke) denies this. Can you see why?

Also, Doepke charges that the Diachronic view lacks explanatory power. Why is this?

(e) Transitivity, Symmetry, and Reflexivity. Doepke claims (almost uncontroversially) that the identity relation is transitive and symmetrical. Also, while Doepke does not explicitly discuss it, identity is traditionally assumed to be reflexive. These relations can be defined as follows:

Transitive: A relation, R, is transitive when: if xRy & yRz, then xRz
Symmetrical: A relation, R, is symmetrical when: if xRy, then yRx
Reflexive: A relation R is reflexive when: if xRy, then xRx

Notice that the identity relation is transitive, symmetrical, and reflexive. If x = y, and y = z, then x = z (transitive). If x = y, then y = x (symmetric). If x = y, then x = x (reflexive).

Doepke claims that the constitution relation is asymmetrical. Do you think he is right here? Why? What view of constitution does he rule out here if he is correct in thinking that constitution is asymmetrical?

Again, Doepke does not discuss reflexivity. Do you think the constitution relation is reflexive? Why or why not?

(f) Doepke makes the distinction between the "is" of identity and the "is" of constitution. How will this affect the set-up of the puzzles? How will it (if it indeed does) affect our commonsense "truisms"?

Also, notice how this distinction saddles nicely with one of our intuitive tests for sortal-hood: an answer to the question "what is it?"

(g) Notice that the Reductivist View (as Doepke describes it) is one way of denying our commonsense principle (1) and (2). Can you see why?


Johnston:

Johnston begins with one of our Puzzles of Objects, Goliath and Lumpl:

Imagine that Sam the sculptor has decided to make a statue of Goliath. However, due to an odd superstition, Sam prefers to sculpt one half of the statue, and then the other, and then he puts them together after the halves are complete. So, on Day 1, he sculpts both the top half and the bottom half of Goliath. On Day 2, he sticks the two halves together and lets the statue harden. On Day 3, he realizes the endeavor was a complete failure, and takes a sledgehammer to the statue, smashing it to smithereens.

Let us call this the First Case.

Johnston claims that in the First Case, Goliath and Lumpl are entirely coincident entities: they "came into being at the same time and ceased to be at the same time." (p. 44 (MC))

Yet clearly the following situation is possible:

Imagine the First Case. Only this time, Sam takes Goliath and rips off his arms and the bottom part of his legs, and dissolves them in acid. Then reshapes arms and lower legs with new bits of clay and adds them to Goliath, so that now Goliath has arms and lower legs.

Let us call this the Second Case.

Johnston thinks it is clear that in the Second Case, Goliath and Lumpl are not entirely coincident entities since Lumpl did not survive parts of it being dissolved in acid, while Goliath did survive the replacement of its arms with new arms.

But if the Second Case is possible, then we know that in the First Case, Goliath is not identical to Lumpl since the second case shows us that Goliath has the modal property of could survive replacement of arms and legs, whereas Lumpl does not. In other words, Goliath and Lumpl have different persistence conditions.

Johnston claims that there are many who want to endorse the following two claims:

(1) In case of complete coincidence, Lumpl is identical to Goliath
(2) Lumpl could not have survived the loss of those of its parts which made up the arms and calves of Goliath. Goliath could have.

But deny this third claim:

(3) Lumpl could not have survived the loss of those of its parts which made up the arms and calves of Goliath. Lumpl could have.

Yet, Johnston claims, (3) follows directly from (2). Consider: by (1), Lumpl = Goliath. By (2), Goliath could have survived the loss of those of its parts which made up the arms and calves of Goliath. So by Leibniz's Law, since L = G, Lumpl could have survived the loss of those of its parts which made up the arms and calves of Goliath. But this directly contradicts the first part of claim (3).

(Note: the ability to substitute co-referential terms without change in truth value is called The Law of Substitutivity of Co-Referential Terms. It will be discussed in class and summarized briefly on the Terms and Concepts page.)

Johnston explains that one way people (e.g., David Lewis) have tried to get out of inferring the contradictory (3) from the intuitively correct (1) and (2) is by appealing to opaque contexts. An opaque context is one in which the Law of Substitutivity of Coreferrential Terms cannot be applied. Lewis claims that "Goliath" is not merely a directly referring term. Rather, it carries with it "a particular counterpart relation or set of necessary and sufficient qualitative conditions for tracing Goliath across worlds..." (45) We will discuss Lewis' view in more detail when we cover Contingent Identity.

Another way that people have tried to get out of being committed to (3) yet granted (1) and (2) is to appeal to a four-dimensional view, where objects are four-dimensional sums of temporal stages. We will be discussing this view later in the semester.

Johnston thinks that neither of the above to ways of denying that (3) follows from (1) and (2) are plausible (just why he thinks this is something we can discuss in more detail in class, and as we discuss the alternative views in more detail).

Rather than try to wriggle out of the inference, Johnston argues, we should reexamine the truth of the claims (1) and (2)--in particular, we should see whether (1) is in fact true. He discusses two arguments for (1), both of which concern issues of mereology and our intuitions concern part-whole relations and identity, and neither of which he thinks stands up to scrutiny. The details of his view and his arguments will be discussed in class, time permitting.

In short: Johnston argues that constitution or the made up of relation is not identity, and so Goliath can be made up of Lump, and yet Goliath is not identical to Lumpl. So he rejects our commonsense principle 6.

Page Last Updated: Feb. 12, 2008
Back to Phil 330 Page
Back to Meg's Teaching Page
Back to Meg's Main Page